3 minute read

Theodicy

Progress And Pessimism



Theodicy was not yet dead, however. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) thought philosophical efforts at theodicy had failed only because they did not see history philosophically. Properly understood, history is "the true theodicy." Like other nineteenth-century accounts of necessary progress, he did not deny the reality of evil. Evil qua evil is a necessary moment in the unfolding of spirit. For Karl Marx (1818–1883) and Friedrich Engels (1820–1895) feudalism was a necessary stage in human history. For Herbert Spencer (1820–1903) the competition that led to the "survival of the fittest" was the best promise for a bright future.



In response, Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) developed his philosophical "pessimism," a deliberate reversal of optimism. This is not the best of all possible worlds, but the worst, a mindless machine of self-inflicted suffering, among whose cleverest devices are precisely the philosophical theories of teleology and progress. All efforts to make life bearable only make things worse. The only hope is to deny the will to live. Schopenhauer claimed that his pessimism made it like Buddhism, a mistaken equation that persists to this day.

In turn, thinkers as varied as Friedrich Nietzsche, William James, and Karl Barth argued for views that acknowledged the impossibility of canceling out the evils of the world and yet affirmed the world. But these views are no longer theodicies—or at least do not claim to be. What makes it possible for us to resist pessimism is not reflection on the experienced order of the world but will (Nietzsche), temperament (James), or grace (Barth).

THEODICIES OF SUFFERING AND GOOD FORTUNE

Max Weber thought that the problem of theodicy was the stimulus for the "rationalization of religious ideas" in all—not just monotheistic—religious traditions. Alongside "theodicies of suffering," accounts of the nature and distribution of misfortune in the world that console those who suffer, Weber discerned another kind of view that reassures those who do not suffer that it is just and right that they be spared. He deems this the "theodicy of good fortune" (ch. 6).

The idea seems to have roots in Marx, but Weber adds the idea that those theodicies that last are those that speak both to the fortunate and to the unfortunate. He thought only three have ever done so: Zoroastrian dualism, the Calvinist understanding of the hidden God (deus absconditus), and the Indian doctrine of karma, "the most complete formal solution of the problem of theodicy (ch. 8).

Weber's is the most impressive effort to expand the meaning of theodicy beyond its monotheistic origins. No longer a problem only for theists, theodicy arises in response to the general problem of the "the incongruity between destiny and merit" (a Kantian problematic), which challenges all human efforts at making theoretical and practical sense of the world. Weber's understanding of theodicy as a species of the problem of meaning has shaped important theories of religion by Clifford Geertz and Peter Berger.

Contemporary debates.

Debate on theodicy has come to be dominated by two very different tendencies. There has been a revival of philosophical theodicy among analytic philosophers of religion, who have moved from attention to the "logical problem of evil" to the "evidential problem of evil." Alvin Plantinga has revived the important distinction between the "defense" of a view against objections and the far more demanding philosophical establishment of that view, which he calls "theodicy," and which he thinks we can do without. On the other hand, the very desire to do theodicy has been condemned as irreligious or ideological. "The disproportion between suffering and every theodicy was shown at Auschwitz with a glaring, obvious clarity," wrote Emmanuel Levinas (p. 162).

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Adams, Marilyn McCord, and Robert Merrihew Adams, eds. The Problem of Evil. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1990.

Bayle, Pierre. "Manichees." In Historical and Critical Dictionary: Selections. Translated by Richard H. Popkin, 144–153. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1991.

Kant, Immanuel. "On the Miscarriage of All Philosophical Trials in Theodicy." Translated by George di Giovanni. In Religion and Rational Theology, edited by Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni, 19–37. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Leibniz, Gottfried W. Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man, and the Origin of Evil. Translated by E. M. Huggard. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1985.

Levinas, Emmanuel. "Useless Suffering." Translated by Richard Cohen. In The Provocation of Levinas: Rethinking the Other, edited by Robert Bernasconi and David Wood, 156–167. London and New York: Routledge, 1988.

Weber, Max. "The Sociology of Religion." Translated by Ephraim Fischoff. In Economy, and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, edited by Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978.

Mark Larrimore

Additional topics

Science EncyclopediaScience & Philosophy: Thallophyta to ToxicologyTheodicy - Early Modern Theodicy, Progress And Pessimism, Theodicies Of Suffering And Good Fortune, Bibliography